What makes a thing “infinite”? (Part 1)

filepicker%2FT2dckkwzQRCqb8bEd4Pz_InfinityIn part 1 we will be focused on its history,in part 2 we will discuss the relationship of infinity with different sciences

infinity ,usually represented by “∞”  often called lemniscate ,is a concept for describing something without limits or boundaries.In mathematics, “infinity” is often treated as if it were a number (i.e., it counts or measures things: “an infinite number of terms”) but it is not the same sort of number as natural or real numbers.

Georg Cantor formalized many ideas related to infinity and infinite sets during the late 19th and early 20th centuries. In the theory he developed, there are infinite sets of different sizes (called cardinalities). For example, the set of integers is countably infinite, while the infinite set of real numbers is uncountable

Beginning of the concept of infinity

As there is no record of earlier civilizations regarding, conceptualizing, or discussing infinity, we will begin the story of infinity with the ancient Greeks. Originally the word apeiron meant unbounded, infinite, indefinite, or undefined. It was a negative, even pejorative word. For the Greeks, the original chaos out of which the world was formed was apeiron. Aristotle thought being infinite was a privation not perfection. It was the absence of limit. Pythagoreans had no traffic with infinity. Everything in their world was number. Indeed, the Pythagoreans associated good and evil with finite and infinite. Though it was not well understood at the time, the Pythagorean discovery of incommensurables, for example √2, would require a clear concept and understanding of infinity.

Yet, to the Greeks, the concept of infinity was forced upon them from the physical world by three traditional observations.

  • Time seems without end.
  • Space and time can be unendingly subdivided.
  • Space is without bound.

History of infinty

One of the earliest appearances of infinity in mathematics regards the ratio between the diagonal and the side of a square. Pythagoras (c. 580–500bce) and his followers initially believed that any aspect of the world could be expressed by an arrangement involving just the whole numbers (0, 1, 2, 3,…), but they were surprised to discover that the diagonal and the side of a square are incommensurable—that is, their lengths cannot both be expressed as whole-number multiples of any shared unit (or measuring stick). In modern mathematics this discovery is expressed by saying that the ratio is irrational and that it is the limit of an endless, nonrepeating decimal series. In the case of a square with sides of length 1, the diagonal is √2, written as 1.414213562…, where the ellipsis (…) indicates an endless sequence of digits with no pattern.

Both Plato (428/427–348/347 bce) and Aristotle (384–322 bce) shared the general Greek abhorrence of the notion of infinity. Aristotle influenced subsequent thought for more than a millennium with his rejection of “actual” infinity (spatial, temporal, or numerical), which he distinguished from the “potential” infinity of being able to count without end. To avoid the use of actual infinity, Eudoxus of Cnidus (c. 400–350 bce) and Archimedes (c. 285–212/211 bce) developed a technique, later known as themethod of exhaustion, whereby an area was calculated by halving the measuring unit at successive stages until the remaining area was below some fixed value (the remaining region having been “exhausted”).

The issue of infinitely small numbers led to the discovery of calculus in the late 1600s by the English mathematician Isaac Newton and the German mathematician Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz. Newton introduced his own theory of infinitely small numbers, or infinitesimals, to justify the calculation ofderivatives, or slopes. In order to find the slope (that is, the change in y over the change in x) for a line touching a curve at a given point (x, y), he found it useful to look at the ratio between dy and dx, wheredy is an infinitesimal change in y produced by moving an infinitesimal amount dx from x. Infinitesimals were heavily criticized, and much of the early history of analysis revolved around efforts to find an alternate, rigorous foundation for the subject. The use of infinitesimal numbers finally gained a firm footing with the development of nonstandard analysis by the German-born mathematician Abraham Robinson in the 1960s.

A more direct use of infinity in mathematics arises with efforts to compare the sizes of infinite sets, such as the set of points on a line (real numbers) or the set of counting numbers. Mathematicians are quickly struck by the fact that ordinary intuitions about numbers are misleading when talking about infinite sizes. Medieval thinkers were aware of the paradoxical fact that line segments of varying lengths seemed to have the same number of points. For instance, draw two concentric circles, one twice the radius (and thus twice the circumference) of the other, as shown in the figure. Surprisingly, each point P on the outer circle can be paired with a unique point P′ on the inner circle by drawing a line from their common centre O to P and labeling its intersection with the inner circle P′. Intuition suggests that the outer circle should have twice as many points as the inner circle, but in this case infinity seems to be the same as twice infinity. In the early 1600s, the Italian scientist Galileo Galilei addressed this and a similar nonintuitive result now known as Galileo’s paradox. Galileo demonstrated that the set of counting numbers could be put in a one-to-one correspondence with the apparently much smaller set of their squares. He similarly showed that the set of counting numbers and their doubles (i.e., the set of even numbers) could be paired up. Galileo concluded that “we cannot speak of infinite quantities as being the one greater or less than or equal to another.” Such examples led the German mathematicianRichard Dedekind in 1872 to suggest a definition of an infinite set as one that could be put in a one-to-one relationship with some proper subset.

The confusion about infinite numbers was resolved by the German mathematician Georg Cantorbeginning in 1873. First Cantor rigorously demonstrated that the set of rational numbers (fractions) is the same size as the counting numbers; hence, they are called countable, or denumerable. Of course this came as no real shock, but later that same year Cantor proved the surprising result that not all infinities are equal. Using a so-called “diagonal argument,” Cantor showed that the size of the counting numbers is strictly less than the size of the real numbers. This result is known as Cantor’s theorem.

To compare sets, Cantor first distinguished between a specific set and the abstract notion of its size, orcardinality. Unlike a finite set, an infinite set can have the same cardinality as a proper subset of itself. Cantor used a diagonal argument to show that the cardinality of any set must be less than the cardinality of its power set—i.e., the set that contains all the given set’s possible subsets. In general, a set with n elements has a power set with 2n elements, and these two cardinalities are different even when n is infinite. Cantor called the sizes of his infinite sets “transfinite cardinals.” His arguments showed that there are transfinite cardinals of endlessly many different sizes (such as the cardinals of the set of counting numbers and the set of real numbers).

The transfinite cardinals include aleph-null (the size of the set of whole numbers), aleph-one (the next larger infinity), and the continuum (the size of real numbers). These three numbers are also written as ℵ0, ℵ1, and c, respectively. By definition ℵ0 is less than ℵ1, and by Cantor’s theorem ℵ1 is less than or equal to c. Along with a principle known as the axiom of choice, the proof method of Cantor’s theorem can be used to ensure an endless sequence of transfinite cardinals continuing past ℵ1 to such numbers as ℵ2 and ℵℵ0.

The continuum problem is the question of which of the alephs is equal to the continuum cardinality. Cantor conjectured that c = ℵ1; this is known as Cantor’s continuum hypothesis (CH). CH can also be thought of as stating that any set of points on the line either must be countable (of size less than or equal to ℵ0) or must have a size as large as the entire space (be of size c).

In the early 1900s a thorough theory of infinite sets was developed. This theory is known as ZFC, which stands for Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory with the axiom of choice. CH is known to be undecidable on the basis of the axioms in ZFC. In 1940 the Austrian-born logician Kurt Gödel was able to show that ZFC cannot disprove CH, and in 1963 the American mathematician Paul Cohen showed that ZFC cannot prove CH. Set theorists continue to explore ways to extend the ZFC axioms in a reasonable way so as to resolve CH. Recent work suggests that CH may be false and that the true size of c may be the larger infinity ℵ2.

Zeno four paradoxes

i will discuss my favourite one  about Achilles and the tortoise so here it is .For all of you wondering who is achilles ,well he was a greek hero.so lets get started.

The tortoise has a head start in a footrace with Achilles. Zeno
argues that the swift Achilles can never catch up, because before he can overtake
the tortoise he must reach the tortoise’s starting point, by which time the tortoise
will have moved on. So he must then cover the distance that the tortoise has
moved, by which time the tortoise will have moved even farther, and so forth.
Achilles has to make an infinite number of steps of this type which, when you look
at it this way, seems impossible. How can you do an infinite number of steps in
finite time?
The problem here is a ridiculously abstract one. One can’t doubt for a moment
that Achilles will overtake the tortoise. The problem consists of trying to think of
it as happening as a result of an infinite number of steps.
The sane answer, it seems to me, is the one Aristotle gave. Don’t. Don’t try to think of it as occurring in an infinite number of steps. You can perhaps—with
a lot of effort—conceive of a million such steps, each requiring a finite time, but
the last ten thousand of the first million steps are almost inconceivably quick—all
ten thousand of them taken together are inconceivably quick, not to mention each
step individually. Is it not fruitless nonsense to try to imagine them as the mere
beginning of an infinite number of steps?
In short, avoid attempts to deal with infinites, either things that are infinitely
small or infinitely large. Often it is useful to deal with potential infinites—for
example to deal with the sequence of numbers 1, 2, 3, … not as an actually
infinite sequence but as a sequence that can be prolonged for as long as you like.
Its potential is infinite in the sense that it never reaches termination, but it is not actually in itself infinite

Number rules the universe.

Pythagoras

 


 

Advertisements

10 thoughts on “What makes a thing “infinite”? (Part 1)

  1. Televisions, DVD players and each other entertainment device today have additional HD-ports.
    If that you are use one camera, a TV (that’s a RCA video input) is obviously recommended.
    Avi to hdmi converter The UD9004 player incorporates a Silicon Optix Realta HQV processing chip that improves DVD
    up-scaling with a near perfect HD level.

    Other cables that happen for being also utilised in audio
    online video gear are optical cables that are used to deliver
    gentle as the sign and coaxial cables. s (both
    LCD and Plasma) took the electronics market by storm, having almost single handedly turning about the retail sales slump inside UK.

    Like

  2. This camera system may be used in indoor or outdoor environments because of it being wireless.

    The Agility System allows users the ability make use of the tablet their way.
    For more Samsung F490 study the above site will aid you are making your buying choice.

    To really get the top and most suitable deal you’ll be able to
    visit UK Online Phone Shop. to complete the repair operates within your car or truck,
    specifically should you’ve got misplaced your key by any possibility.

    Like

  3. Being female means that some mothers like to dress you in dresses and cute
    shoes and discourage you from climbing trees.
    some people take advantage of the phrase, “Well you knew I was like this when you married me”, or
    “I’ve been like this all my life. Acronym tbt

    For the average user, the minimum and recommended system requirements listed on a product’s retail box is an important piece of information. “The task ahead of you can always be overcome by the power within you.

    Like

  4. I got Minecraft yesterday evening because it really appeared to be a creative game.

    Minecraft may also be played in “creative” mode,
    where the player uses mineral resources to produce structures
    from a type.xt% try minecraft for free online

    I got Minecraft yesterday evening because it really appeared
    to be a creative game. Minecraft may also be played in “creative” mode, where the player
    uses mineral resources to produce structures from a type.xt%

    Like

  5. Woah! I’m really enjoying the template/theme of this website.
    It’s simple, yet effective. A lot of times it’s challenging
    to get that “perfect balance” between usability and visual appearance.

    I must say you have done a great job with this. Also, the blog loads very
    fast for me on Firefox. Excellent Blog!

    Like

Leave a Reply

Fill in your details below or click an icon to log in:

WordPress.com Logo

You are commenting using your WordPress.com account. Log Out / Change )

Twitter picture

You are commenting using your Twitter account. Log Out / Change )

Facebook photo

You are commenting using your Facebook account. Log Out / Change )

Google+ photo

You are commenting using your Google+ account. Log Out / Change )

Connecting to %s